This isn't something I'm interested in but thought it'd be interesting to the
cool Sudoroom folks
http://www.pbs.org/newshour/making-sense/column-the-case-for-employee-owned…
Column: The case for employee-owned companies
Making Sen$e’s segment on the 100 percent worker-owned New Belgium Brewing stirred some
interest in the concept of employee stock ownership. David Ellerman explains the theory
behind employee-owned companies. Photo by Flickr user +Russ.
Editor’s Note: Our story on Colorado’s 100 percent worker-owned company New Belgium
Brewing has stirred some interest in the concept of employee stock ownership. We didn’t
have time, however, to explore a particularly provocative and arguably profound voice on
the issue, David Ellerman, based at the University of California, Riverside.
Ellerman has for years made an argument as startling as it is hard to refute: “the labor
theory of property.” It’s that employees should own the firms they work for because of
very simple logic: If they’re responsible for the consequences of their actions while on
the job ― committing a crime, say ― how can it be that they’re not responsible for the
positive things they do, such as making money?
Ellerman’s writing on “the labor theory of property” has mostly been for a technical
audience. I asked him if he wouldn’t mind trying to make his argument in a more popular
way for the Making Sen$e page. Here’s what he sent us.
― Paul Solman, Economics Correspondent
You are called in for jury duty. You protest to the judge that you are not a lawyer. How
can you be expected to make a legal decision? But the judge points out that the jury is
not there to interpret the law but to make a decision about the facts. Is the defendant in
fact responsible for committing the crime as charged ― or not? Guilty or not guilty?
The legal system then assigns the legal responsibility according to the jury’s decision
about the factual responsibility.
That is the basic principle of justice: assign the legal responsibility to the people who
are in fact responsible for the deeds in question.
With that principle of justice, injustice falls into two categories:
assigning legal responsibility to a defendant who was not in fact responsible for the
crime ― that is, convicting an innocent person, or
not assigning legal responsibility to a defendant who was in fact responsible ― that is,
not convicting a guilty person.
There is something else to notice about the basic norm of justice. Criminals have their
“tools of the trade,” which can be quite important in committing crimes. But tools cannot
be factually responsible for committing a crime, only people. For example, guns can’t be
responsible for killing people, but people find it much easier to kill someone,
deliberately or accidentally, if guns are available. Thus, regardless of the tools,
instruments or other things being used in committing a crime, only the people committing
the crime are in fact responsible for it.
This basic principle of justice ― assign legal responsibility according to factual
responsibility ― is used by the courts of law, but there’s no reason this principle should
be applied only to negative results like crimes or misdeeds. When people deliberately
produce something positive, shouldn’t they also get the legal “credit” or “ownership” of
that result? The justice principle can thus be seen as applying to both positive and
negative results of all responsible human actions.
But there is a problem ― our current economic system does not follow the justice
principle. In the previous system ― prior to the arrival of modern democracy ― masters
could own other people involuntarily (the slaves). Thankfully, that system was abolished.
But voluntariness was not the key issue since the contract to voluntarily sell oneself
into slavery was also abolished along with involuntary slavery.
In the current economic system, people rent themselves out to an “employer.” As the late
Paul Samuelson of MIT, the first American Nobel Prize winner in economics, put it in his
widely-used textbook:
Since slavery was abolished, …[a] man is not even free to sell himself: he must rent
himself at a wage.
This use of the word “rent” may be jarring, but it is accurate. Americans refer to “rental
cars” and the British refer to “hire cars,” but both are talking about the same thing
where the renter is not buying the car, but only buying some of its services. Renting
something is buying its services.
Our current employment system of renting, hiring or employing people conflicts with the
justice principle. In a factory operating under the employment relation, the people
working in the factory jointly produce whatever is the product. Consider a company that
produces widgets, for example. Those widgets are the positive results of their responsible
actions. But to produce the widgets, they must jointly use up raw materials, intermediate
goods, machinery and other resources. Those used-up resources are the negative results of
their responsible actions.
But the people working in the enterprise do not jointly have legal ownership of the
widgets they produce, and they do not jointly bear the expenses for the resources (raw
materials, intermediate goods, etc.) they use to produce the widgets. Instead, it is the
employer who owns the widgets and pays off the non-labor costs for the used resources. The
rented people, the employees, are seen simply as the providers of just another resource ―
known in this case, as labor services. The employer pays off the liability for using that
resource by paying the labor costs ― the wages and salaries.
Hence, the employment system seems to involve a mismatch between legal responsibility and
factual responsibility. While the positive and negative legal responsibility goes to the
(working or absentee) employer, the positive and negative factual responsibility is with
both the working employer and the employees. The renting of people certainly seems to
violate the standard justice principle of assigning legal responsibility in accordance to
factual responsibility.
But the employees are said to voluntarily give up their responsibility for the results of
their “labor services.” How can one “give up” factual responsibility?
Consider the case of an employee who commits a crime at the instruction of the employer.
Certainly then the employee really does want to voluntarily give up and transfer away any
factual responsibility for the results of his labor services. But there is no such escape.
The legal system then recognizes that the “employment” of one’s own actions cannot be
voluntarily transferred to another person. One could transfer the use of one’s car or
shovel to another person, but not the “employment” of one’s self. As a British law book on
the employer-employee relation puts it (using the old-speak of “master and servant”):
All who participate in a crime with a guilty intent are liable to punishment. A master and
servant who so participate in a crime are liable criminally, not because they are master
and servant, but because they jointly carried out a criminal venture and are both
criminous.
But what factually changes when the venture being jointly carried out is not criminal? Do
the employees suddenly turn into non-responsible robots employed by their employer?
Presumably employees are just as much factually responsible for their deliberate actions
when they produce widgets as when they commit crimes.
It is the response of the legal system that changes ― when no crime is committed, the
legal system sees no reason to intervene to explicitly apply the justice principle it has
so clearly established in ordinary trials. The system then accepts “obeying the employer”
as fulfilling the employment contract. There seems to be no breach of the contract ― even
though “obeying the employer” didn’t get the criminal employee off the hook. But with no
breach or crimes involved, the legal system is silent. It does not intervene to apply the
justice principle as it does in a criminal or civil trial.
The end result is that the employer ends up paying off all the costs of the used-up
resources, including the wage payments for the employees’ labor services, and thus owning
all the widgets produced. But the employer is not in fact solely responsible for using up
those resources or for producing that product ― so this adds up to a violation of the
justice principle. The justice principle says that all the expenses for the used-up
resources and all the revenues from owning and selling the widgets should go to the
factually responsible party, which would be all the people working in the enterprise.
This violation is built into the whole system of renting people ― even if voluntarily.
Should that be surprising? We are accustomed to condemn slavery for being involuntary, but
would owning other people be okay if it were voluntary? Perhaps the basic problem with
owning other people was not whether it was involuntary or voluntary, but that it treated
people as things. And that is still a problem with the renting of people in our economy.
It treats the rented people like non-responsible things whose use or employment can be
voluntarily transferred from one person to another like a car or shovel.
How can the problem be fixed? Today, the renting, hiring or employing of people seems as
“natural” as owning people did before the 19th century. In either case, most people in
such a society take it for granted. But what if the abolitionists’ achievement of
abolishing the owning of other people was followed up with the “neo-abolitionist” goal of
abolishing the renting of other people? It would mean that all the people working together
in a given enterprise would be the owners or members of that enterprise. They would
jointly own what they jointly produce, and they would jointly pay off the costs for all
the resources that they jointly used. In short, they would jointly own both the positive
and negative “fruits of their labor” so private property would be re-founded on the
justice principle.
The conservative British thinker, Lord Eustace Percy, put the matter very well back in
1944.
Here is the most urgent challenge to political invention ever offered to the jurist and
the statesman. The human association which in fact produces and distributes wealth, the
association of workmen, managers, technicians and directors, is not an association
recognised by the law. The association which the law does recognize ― the association of
shareholders, creditors and directors ― is incapable of production and is not expected by
the law to perform these functions. We have to give law to the real association, and to
withdraw meaningless privilege from the imaginary one.
It was previously noted that the factually responsible party is the community of all the
people working in the enterprise, which Lord Percy called the “human association which in
fact produces and distributes wealth.” That community is not even recognized as a legal
party in the current system. “The association which the law does recognise” is (typically)
the corporation-as-employer in the employer-employer relationship.
The closest legal form we have today where the factually responsible party is also the
legally responsible party would be worker cooperatives (like the Mondragon cooperatives in
the Basque country in Spain) or the “employee-owned” companies like the 7,000 or so
Employee Stock Ownership Plans (ESOPs) across the United States (at least where 100
percent of the stock is in the ESOP trust for the employees). With those legal forms, the
“association which the law does recognise” is also the “human association which in fact
produces and distributes wealth.” That arrangement satisfies the justice principle.
Sent from my iPhone